Deductive, Inductive, and Abductive Reasoning Explained

Deduction Vs. Induction vs. Abduction

Deductive, inductive, and abductive reasoning are three basic reasoning types. In simple terms, deductive reasoning deals with certainty, inductive reasoning with probability, and abductive reasoning with guesswork.

These three methods of reasoning, which all other reasoning types essentially fall under or are a mix of, can be a little tricky to illustrate with examples… because each can work a variety of ways (thus, any one example tends to be misleading;  keep that in mind as you read through the examples below).

The core concepts to remember aredeductive reasoning deals with certainty and involves reasoning toward certain conclusions, inductive reasoning deals with probability and involves reasoning toward likely conclusions based on data, and abductive reasoning deals with guesswork, involves reasoning toward possible conclusions based on guesswork (a best guess), and it is a type of reasoning that is used in formulating a hypothesis for further testing.

In other words, Abduction is forming a hypothesis, induction is like analyzing the data from testing a hypothesis, and deduction would be used in drawing certain logical conclusions from the data gathered.

To put it another way, deduction deals with what is the case for sure, induction deals with what is likely the case, and abduction deals with a best guess as to what could be the case based on a limited set of information.

To put it another way, if one has a group of premises (statements), any conclusion they can draw from those premises that is logically certain is found via deductive reasoning, any conclusion they can draw that is likely given those premises is found via inductive reasoning, and any conclusion that draws not just from what the premises state but from what could also be the case but is not explicitly known for sure (and thus involves guesswork) is found via abduction.

If that doesn’t work for you, let’s try using some classic syllogistic reasoning examples (NOTE: for the purposes of this page, we want to assume all our premises are true; we are discussing methods of reasoning, not testing the validity of premises).

Deductive Inductive Abductive
Major Premise All Men are Mortal Most Greeks Have Beards Observation: That Man Has a Beard
Minor Premise Socrates is a Man Socrates is a Greek Known Fact: Most Greeks Have Beards
Conclusion (Inference) It is certain that: Socrates is Mortal (this is logically certain given the premises; if all men are mortal, then Socrates being a man, must be mortal. Here, you can see that if a premise is false, deduction can produce false conclusions). It is “likely” that: Socrates has a beard (given the premises, the conclusion can be assigned a likelihood; this argument isn’t very compelling, but to explain that quality of induction here would be a rabbit hole). Perhaps: This Man is Greek (a hypothesis based on an observation and a known fact; we can gather inductive evidence to test this hypothesis, for example, by gathering more information about the origin of the man).

As you can see above, when we reasoned toward a logically certain conclusion, it was deduction. When our premises only pointed toward a likelihood, it was induction. And when your premises led to a question/guess, it was abduction.

Reasoning/Argument is all a bit more complex than that, but that is the gist of the three main types of reasoning/argument.

In Summary:

  • Deductive reasoning deals with certainty, involving reasoning from general principles to specific conclusions. If the premises are true, the conclusion must be true. Example: All humans are mortal (premise), Socrates is a human (premise), therefore, Socrates is mortal (conclusion).
  • Inductive reasoning deals with probability, involving reasoning from specific observations to broader generalizations. The conclusion is likely, but not guaranteed, to be true. Example: You observe that the sun has risen every day of your life, so you conclude that the sun will rise tomorrow.
  • Abductive reasoning deals with guesswork, involving reasoning from incomplete information to form a hypothesis or a best guess. Example: Your car won’t start in the morning. Based on your knowledge of cars and the circumstances, you hypothesize that the battery is dead.

If that still doesn’t make sense, try watching the following videos:

How to Argue – Philosophical Reasoning: Crash Course Philosophy #2

How to Argue – Philosophical Reasoning: Crash Course Philosophy #2How to Argue – Induction & Abduction: Crash Course Philosophy #3

An Example of Inductive, Deductive, and Abductive Reasoning in the Form of a Story

Consider it this way, in the form of a story:

Sherlock arrives at a crime scene and finds a body, blood, footprints, and a knife. Using abductive reasoning, he hypothesizes, “perhaps the knife is a murder weapon and was used to murder this person?” As, if that was the case, the observation would make sense (comparing an observation to a known fact or rule to come up with a best guess of what might be the case for the situation to make sense is abduction).

Then he checks the fingerprints and the blood and runs them through a database, the prints belong to a known criminal, and the blood is from two people, both the criminal and the body. Watson (a doctor) checks and confirms the victim died from the knife wound.

Using inductive reasoning, Sherlock concludes that it is likely, but not certain, that the known criminal murdered this victim with the knife and fled the scene. He has solid evidence, his hypothesis seems correct, but he doesn’t have certainty (Sherlock compared facts that led to a conclusion with a probable, but not logically certain, answer; the premises led to a probable conclusion, thus it was induction).

Sherlock then spots a camera.

Playing the tape recorded by the camera, Sherlock clearly sees the criminal stab the victim with a knife and exit the crime scene leaving everything as it exists now (he then plays the tape all the way to the moment he saw the tape; the victim never moved and no one else entered the scene).

Since Sherlock saw the stabbing happen and saw no other person enter the crime scene, he can use deductive reasoning to conclude with logical certainty that if all is as it appears, then it was the case that the criminal murdered the victim with the knife.

The victim was alive, the victim is now dead, the camera shows the criminal stabbing the victim.

Of course, that said, visual evidence like this doesn’t produce certainty that the criminal committed the crime. It only produces a high degree of certainty, a probability. Thus, here we must carefully say 1. the visual evidence is inductive evidence that provides a high degree of certainty, 2. logically speaking, if it is the criminal on camera committing the murder, then the criminal must be the murderer (a redundant and tautological point, but a logically certain one).

Knowing this, Sherlock can also deduce that Watson was not the murderer. After all, Watson was with Sherlock, and only the criminal and victim were on camera during the murder. Sherlock deduces some logically certain and almost redundant things based on the evidence, which is a hallmark of deductive reasoning.

If the criminal is the murderer, then logically Watson cannot be (Sherlock deduced some logically certain and almost redundant things based on the evidence, this is deduction… a matter of only what is logically certain, not a matter of what seems highly likely given evidence of any sort).

Sherlock, being highly confident in his conclusion based on all his reasoning and fact-finding, then tells Watson, “the criminal murdered the victim with the knife.”

Finally, when Watson asked how he solved the case, Sherlock, for once, answered honestly, “the same way one truly solves any case, using a mix of abduction, induction, and deduction, my dear Watson.”

That “fun story includes only some of ways to illustrate the reasoning types, their similarities, and their differences. Instead of talking about Sherlock, I could have talked about rain and clouds, or about Socrates’ mortality and beard, but one has to start somewhere my dear reader!

Below are some longer explanations (see even longer ones here). The idea of this page isn’t to write an essay on reason or talk about every possible reasoning type (see our section on logic and reason for that sort of thing), it is to translate the gist of what one might consider the three main reasoning types 😉

NOTE: In the above story I stressed the phrase “if all is as it appears” for a reason. As noted above, observing something happen doesn’t make it certain, it only makes it very likely to have been the case (consider, the person on camera could have been in disguise, the video could have been edited, or the figure in the camera could be a robot being controlled off-screen, etc). Dealing with that which is very likely, like what Sherlock saw on the video, is still a matter of induction, not deduction. You can use deduction to conclude that a black cat is not white (since we are saying the cat is black, we can deduce that it is logically the case that the cat is not white). However, if you see a black cat you cannot know for certain that the cat is not white, it could have its hair died, your eyes could not be working correctly, etc. The key here is that logical certainty is about what must logically be true given the premises, not about what seems certain from observation.

NOTE: There is a fine line between induction and abduction. The line is so fine one might consider abduction a certain type of induction used to formulate a hypothesis. I’ll discuss this more below, but if you are confused between the two, I would suggest that is natural. The key is largely found in the type of conclusion drawn.

Another Other Way to Look at Deductive, Inductive, and Abductive Reasoning

Imagine you have a set of data. Logical truths, rules, statistics, etc. (a mix of all the different types of data you can imagine; which one generally gets from observation and measurement), AKA “premises.”

Now imagine you mix and match data points that seem to connect to draw conclusions from those data points, organizing them in a way that creates a “logical argument” like this:

  1. Data point (AKA premise) #1
  2. Data point #2
  3. Conclusion.

Now consider:

  • Any logically certain conclusion you can draw from comparing those data points is deductive, any likely conclusion you can draw is inductive, and any hypothesis you can form is abductive.
  • The type of conclusion you draw acts as a tell (a hint) for the reasoning type used (as, for example, if your reasoning is done properly, only deductive reasoning can produce a logically certain conclusion).
  • Any data point that is a logically certain truth, like “black cats are black,” might be thought of to be in the deductive category, and any data point with even a hint of probability, like “9 in 10 tests performed showed a positive result” or “all ravens we observed have been black” might be thought to be inductive in nature.
  • The way one reasons toward a conclusion and the type of conclusion help to define the reasoning type. Sometimes the same data can be reasoned through using different reasoning methods. If the argument is 1. Some cats are black, 2. No cats are green. I can conclude: deduction = this cat is not green, induction = this cat might be black, or abduction = perhaps something in cat genetics stop cats from being green, yet allows them to be black?

In other words, these are just three different ways to work through data to draw different types of conclusions.

Since deductive arguments / conclusions tend to be redundant, like “black cats are black” or “since some tests show negative results, not all tests are positive,” most reasoning ends up being inductive in nature. All that means is that one makes observations / takes measurements (or collects someone else’s) and then draws likely conclusion given those observations / measurements.

Induction is simply drawing likely conclusions from data (where each data point, like lab tests or citations helps to increase the certainty of a conclusion) and deduction is simply deducing logically certain truths.

Meanwhile, in a case where there isn’t enough evidence to support a conclusion, we can formulate a hypothesis using abduction. For example: I observe that this bird is white, I know that ravens are typically black, therefore it follows that this probably isn’t a raven. My hypothesis, or best guess, is that this bird is not a Raven (then we would build a case for it not being a raven to try to show that it wasn’t a raven using induction and deduction). In this sense abduction is essentially a form of induction where one doesn’t have enough data to draw a conclusion (but has the grounds for coming up with a hypothesis to which further testing can be applied).

Simply put,

  • Something that is self-evident and logically certain is deductive. Meanwhile, deductive reasoning is when we reason through data points toward a logically certain conclusion.
  • When a case is being built with evidence to find the likelihood that something is the case it is inductive. Meanwhile, inductive reasoning is when we reason through data points toward probable conclusions.
  • And, when the evidence isn’t there to support a conclusion, we can formulate a hypothesis using abduction. Meanwhile, abductive reasoning is the process of comparing these points and coming up with the best explanation.

So, abduction is guessing based on data, induction is determining likelihood based on data, and deduction is the act of determining redundant, tautological, logically certain truths.

Then, since abduction is just a guess in need of induction and deduction, and deduction is almost redundant, induction ends up being the glue that holds everything together and tells us what is likely true about the world…. yet since induction alone can never produce certainty and doesn’t lend itself to imagination (like abduction does) the three forms end up working together rather well when it comes to formulating arguments, critical thinking, and finding truths.

Deduction, induction, and abduction are like three parts of the same puzzle, and all formal reasoning is done using them and only them. Without abduction there is no hypothesis, without induction no testing, and without deduction no way to falsify; i..e. not only is there no logic or reason without these methods, there is no science (and essentially no philosophy). They are simply names for the aspects of human reason.

Deductive, Inductive, and Abductive Reasoning Defined

Above I tried to illustrate the types of reasoning by discussing them together, at this point it’ll likely help to offer full definitions of each:

Abduction: The reasoning method that deals with guesswork and produces a possible explanation. It is forming a hypothesis or likely explanation. The surprising fact, C, is observed; But if A were true, C would be a matter of course, Hence, there is reason to suspect that A is true. Ex.  I see my dog’s bowl is empty; if my dog ate the food this would be the case, the likely explanation for the dog food being missing is that the dog ate the food. My hypothesis is the dog ate the food.

Induction: The reasoning method that deals with probability and produces a likelihood. It reasons from specific facts and probable rules “up” toward probable conclusions that don’t necessarily follow from the premises. It looks for patterns in data, reasoning by consistency and attempts to build a strong argument by collecting data that tells are compelling story. It is inferring B from A where B does not necessarily follow from A. Ex. Most A are B, and this C is A, therefore this C is likely B. Ex. Most dogs eat dog food, my dog is like most dogs, my dog would have eaten the dog food (that isn’t logically certain, it is just very likely).

Deduction: The reasoning method that deals with certainty and produces a certain truth value. It is a reasoning method that deals with certain conclusions (logically certain inferences). It reasons from certain rules and facts “down” to logically certain conclusions that necessarily follow the premises of an argument. It is inferring B from A when and only when B is a formal logical consequence of A. Ex. All A are B, and all C are A, therefore all C must be B. Ex. All dogs are mammals, all mammals need food, therefore all dogs need to eat food (a logically certain truth; almost redundant AKA tautological).

Here is everything above in one example:

The dog’s food was in the bowl, but the food is now it is missing (deduction; food was in bowl, food now not in bowl, certain truths). The likely explanation for the dog food being missing is that the dog ate the food (abduction; a hypothesis was formed as a best guess given the observation and that which is often the case). I am going to compile some inductive evidence to prove the dog ate the food. 1. the dog doesn’t seem to want to eat any more (he seems to be full). 2. he has dog food around his mouth. 3. when I ask him if he ate the food he looks guilty. I’ll conclude the dog likely ate the food (induction; I used inductive evidence to show it is likely that the dog ate the food; it isn’t certain, just likely). Oh wait… I just checked the security footage and it shows the cat ate the food while the dog sat there and looked sad. Since the cat did eat the food , the dog could not have eaten the food… that is logically certain conclusion (deduction).

FACTCharles Sanders Peirce came up with Abduction to describe this odd sort of non-deduction that wasn’t exactly induction as it had been known. Otherwise deduction and induction are longstanding concepts worked on by philosphers over the years.

Deductive, Inductive, and Abductive Reasoning in the Scientific Method

The scientific method uses a mix of abduction (formulating hypotheses AKA making educated guesses), inductive reasoning (comparing data to draw likely conclusions AKA testing hypotheses and formulating theories), and deductive reasoning (for example, using data to falsify a hypothesis necessarily based on inductive evidence).

In this way deduction tends to be rooted in rationalism (working with what is logically necessary given the data), inductive reasoning tends to be rooted in empirical observation and measurement (working with what is likely given the data), and abduction is rooted in both (using inductive and deductive reasoning to reason by analogy, to formulate hypotheses).

In other words, how abduction, induction, and deduction work together in the scientific method (and often in reasoning in general) is like this: abduction forms the hypothesis, induction tests the hypothesis and helps us deduce what likely is, and then deduction helps us to understand what is logically certain given the inductive evidence (potentially “proving” or disproving our hypothesis).

Other Examples of Deductive, Inductive, and Abductive Reasoning

Here are some other examples of abduction, induction, and deduction so you can see other examples of what the above arguments could look like:

Alt. Deduction Ex. Premise 1: If it’s raining then it’s cloudy. Premise 2: If it’s cloudy then it’s not bright. Conclusion: It’s raining so it’s not bright.

Alt. Deduction Ex. Premise 1: It’s raining. Premise 2: It’s cloudy. Conclusion: It can rain and be cloudy at the same time.

Alt. Induction Ex. Premise 1: If it’s raining then it’s cloudy. Premise 2: It’s probably raining. Conclusion: It’s probably cloudy.

Alt. Induction Ex. Premise 1: If it’s raining then it’s probably cloudy. Premise 2: It’s raining. Conclusion: It’s probably cloudy.

Alt. Abduction Ex. Premise 1: If it’s raining then it’s cloudy.. Premise 2: It’s wet and raining. Conclusion: Perhaps when it’s cloudy it’s wet?

Here is another example

Abduction. 1+_=2  (no one knows what _ is, could be a formula, could be a single number; however, if it were 1 then it would all make sense… 1 is a solid guess).

Deduction. 1+1=x  (it is logically certain that 1+1= 2; in terms of formal logic, x is certainly 2)

Induction. x equals 1 or 2 99% of the time, y equals 1 or 2 95% of the time AND it is the case that x+y=3 (it is likely that x is 1 and y is 2 or vice versa).

Notes on Semantics: In common language when people say “deduction” or “deduce” they mean “draw an inference using either deduction or induction.” If Sherlock considers probable evidence at a crime scene, but doesn’t witness the crime, and then he “deduces” (draws the inference) that it was “Mr. Mustard in the Parlor with the Candlestick,” he is using “induction” (he is comparing probable evidence to draw a probable conclusion about “what was the case”). Meanwhile, if Sherlock “deduces” (draws the inference) that “the victim was a bachelor, and was therefore was necessarily unmarried… because he is a bachelor (as unmarried is a property of all bachelors),” that is “deduction.” Meanwhile, if Sherlock “deduces” that it was the case that the victim was targeted because he was a bachelor, as other bachelors had recently be targeted, that would be abductive reasoning (which formulates a speculative hypothesis based on an interesting observation).

It Is About the Conclusions and the Way Facts are Reasoned Through… not the Qualities or Order of Premises

The point above being, it really doesn’t matter what order subjects and predicates are in, or the exact qualities and flavors of the premisses. If the line of reasoning deals with certainty, it is deduction. If it deals with probability it is induction. If it deals with best guesses, it is abduction.

Likewise, if the conclusion is certain, it is deduction. Probable, induction. A hypothesis or likely explanation, abduction.

I would say the above is true… even to the extent that we would consider abduction to certainly not be a form of deduction, but to essentially be a style of of induction where a weak inductive argument seems likely so we go ahead and apply further testing to the conclusion.

The reality is, in the inductive argument below, one can draw a deductive conclusion, an inductive conclusion, and an abductive conclusion given the inductive evidence (and that hints that it is the method and the conclusions drawn that tell us what type of reasoning it is, not just, or sometimes not at all, the qualities of the premises).

Deductive: Socrates is a mortal man (tautological necessary truth, simply a result of logical analysis). Inductive: All men are likely mortal like Socrates is (a likely rule based on a synthesis of the inductive evidence); NOTE: This is a weak argument, the evidence would become stronger the more instances we look at (so if we looked at 100 men, we could be more sure that all men are mortal). Abductive: Perhaps all men are mortal like Socrates is (a hypothesis gleaned from comparing an interesting observation to a fact).

TIP: See the classic syllogistic reasoning examples below. The problem with them is that while they work well to illustrate deduction, they only illustrate one style of induction, and they also don’t do a great job of differentiating between abduction and induction. It is the classic example that is paired with reasoning, but it doesn’t tell the full story (which means it can be confusing).

Deductive Inductive Abductive
Major Premise All Men are Mortal (a certain fact about a class of things, could also be any certain fact about a specific thing or class of things.) Socrates is Mortal (a fact about a specific thing, could also be a probable rule about a class of things.) All Men are Mortal (a certain fact about a class of things, could be any type of premise.)
Minor Premise Socrates is a Man (a certain fact about a specific thing, could also be a certain fact about a class of things.) Socrates is a Man (a certain fact about a specific thing, could also be a probable rule about a class of things.) Socrates is a Mortal (could be any interesting observation or idea.)
Conclusion (Inference) It is certain that: Socrates is Mortal (Deduce a fact about a specific thing or class of things; produces a certain fact about a specific thing or class of things.) It is likely that: All Men are Mortal (Infer a probable fact about a specific thing or class of things; produces a likely fact or rule about a specific thing or class of things.) Perhaps: Socrates is a Man (Speculate a connection between the interesting observation and the certain or probable fact, rule, or observation, speculating a connection between the two premises; produces a speculative hypothesis.)

NOTE: On this page you should consider every proposition (every statement in an argument) to be true. The study of arguments forms and types is not the study of the truth of specific propositions.

A Few Other Notes:

Bottom Up vs. Top Down: Induction is often called bottom-up reasoning because it generally starts with specifics facts/observations/measurements and/or probable rules (gleaned from comparing specifics) and reasons toward a generalization (a probable rule or likelihood).  It is often called top-down reasoning because it generally starts with a certain rule about a class of things, compares that to a certain fact about a specific thing, and then reasons down towards a certain conclusion about a specific thing (although it can reason from specifics to specifics or rules to rules too. That said, one can do the inverse of any reasoning type (as noted above). For example with inverse induction, we would start with the conclusion and look for facts that proved the conclusion with certainty. Or with inverse deduction, we start with certain facts and look for a certain theory to support them. Bottom-up and top-down terminology aside, working with certain conclusions that follow from the premises only is deduction, and working likely truths that don’t necessarily follow from the premises is induction. Likewise, no matter what direction you go, comparing observations and specific facts to produce a speculative hypothesis is abduction.

Analysis / Rationalism and Synthesis / Empiricism: Deduction is a type of analysis (breaking a whole into parts) that is closely related to rationalism (the world of ideas), as it looks at what is logically and necessarily true about a given system (in this case a set of propositions; an argument). Induction is a type of synthesis (combining parts into a whole) that is closely related to empiricism (the world of material objects), because it compares data points that are generally obtained through observation/measurement to better understand how data does and doesn’t connect.

Author: Thomas DeMichele

Thomas DeMichele is the content creator behind ObamaCareFacts.com, FactMyth.com, CryptocurrencyFacts.com, and other DogMediaSolutions.com and Massive Dog properties. He also contributes to MakerDAO and other cryptocurrency-based projects. Tom's focus in all...

Leave a comment

We'll never share your email with anyone else.

Thanks for writing this. It’s extremely helpful! 🙂

Reply

amazing. very well written

Reply

This article explains each type of reasoning in a way that is very easily understood. After reading from a textbook, and watching a video lecture on the subject I was still somewhat confused. I decided to research to find a simple explanation. Your article was just that. Thank you.

Reply